Tuesday, June 25, 2013

Crime and Punishment




There’s been an idea circulating for some time that retributive justice is morally and logically founded upon the fact that we possess a thing called free will - some assumed weird mechanism that disconnects human behaviour from the normal cause-and-effect based evolution of nature. If, after all, human actions were really ‘just’ the result of mechanistic microscopic processes, then whatever we do would be entirely determined by the laws of physics and the configuration of our environment. And if this were really so, then whatever somebody does is a consequence of the fact that they could not have willfully done otherwise, in which case there is no sense in which a person can be blamed for doing wrong. And if culpability can not be established, then doesn't the validity of punishment look suspect? So prevalent is this idea that it forms a major part of contemporary legal philosophy.

Not only is this idea of free will completely nonsensical, but the connection between it and the justice of retribution is totally unfounded. Vengeance, after all is really just an expression of anger. Is anger rational? Is it a reliable, systematic producer of well judged behaviour? Or is it merely a crude and ancient heuristic moderator of human interaction that in a modern, enlightened era, we could do with much less of?

There is simply no logical link between culpability and the righteousness of retributive punishment,  which somehow ‘repays a debt to society.’ Try to derive this principle logically, and you will find it impossible without directly assuming the desired outcome among the required premises. 

What we must see instead is that, in line with more agreeable consequentialist moral philosophies, the only appropriate consideration when assigning juridical interventions is: what actions will lead to a better society for us, and for our children to grow up in? In this case, the problem justifying enforced treatment (e.g. imprisonment) upon somebody who ‘couldn't have acted any other way’ disappears completely. The enforced treatment is only indirectly determined by the person’s actions, and is wholly derived from what we would like the world to look like in the future. The relevance of past behaviour is limited to the extent to which it serves as a predictor of future behaviour. What are traditionally viewed as punishments - justice administered for the satisfaction of the victims - become more properly viewed as treatments, designed to minimize the cost for society of a person’s demonstrated antisocial tendencies. 

The desire for revenge against a person who has committed wrongs against us is likely to be at least partly due to population genetics, naturally selected for self-preserving behaviour (it is advantageous for me to create an environment in which another’s bad behaviour toward me makes life uncomfortable for them), but the idea linking this concept of justice to free will seems to be far more memetic than genetic: it is a matter of culture.

The concept that free will is necessary and sufficient to entail the punishment of moral failing seems to date back to Aristotle, in Nicomachean Ethics. I’m no scholar of Aristotle, but to me its not clear whether for him the appropriateness of blame has a consequentialist or an absolutist foundation - are praise and blame desirable because they make certain modes of future behaviour more likely, or because they try to balance what has happened in the past?

If I had to speculate on the reason for the cultural success of the notion specifically linking retribution to free will, I’d guess that it was found to come in very useful when dictators wrestled with the seemingly contradictory goals of being loved, yet being utterly feared.

How can you be brutally violent against your enemies, while remaining admired by the remaining population? One way would seem to be to claim that violence against certain people is morally just, even necessary. “It made me cry to do that to him, but his crimes left me no choice.” Such pious adherence to absolute moral principle, even when it demands the most unpleasant actions, might even elevate a thug to saintly status, bringing joyous tears to the eyes of his devoted followers.

In the course of time, it may be that neuroscience, experimental psychology, and the social sciences will come to the conclusion that a better society is generally one in which people’s innate desire for vengeance is somewhat fulfilled (I doubt this, as I’ll explain shortly), but this would not undermine the principle that treatment of criminals should be determined on purely consequentialist grounds. If it happened to be that this desire was so strong, and so innate that no amount of cultural evolution could remove it, and that the frustration of unplacated victims of crime was so intense as to threaten civil unrest, then a retributive element may need to be restored, but the ultimate reasoning would be the rational evaluation of different courses of action, and selection in favour of those strategies determined to be in society’s best interests.

The debate between absolutist and consequentialist moral philosophies has been going on for a long time: consequentialism goes at least as far back as Machiavelli, around 500 years ago. Absolutism goes much further back, and persists still. This is really quite surprising - its not a difficult problem to solve. All morality is manifestly consequentialist, no matter what we might profess. 

Wait a moment, ‘thou shalt not kill.’ It doesn't get much more absolutist than that does it? No, it doesn't  But just how absolutist is that exactly?

For starters, no society implements principles like this in the strict absolutist way. Christians believe that this basic rule, ‘thou shalt not kill’ was handed to them by their personal deity: thou shalt not kill means that killing is absolutely wrong, under all circumstances - no exceptions allowed. Its never stopped Christian nations going to war when they felt like it. It never prevented Christian inquisitors burning people at the stake when the winter nights were dark and cold. All assumed absolutist principles have always been tacitly appended with a host of additional clauses beginning with the word ‘Unless...’ This is pure consequentialism.

Well, maybe those people adding their arbitrary ‘unless’ clauses were simply bad moralists. Thou shalt not kill is a good rule after all, right? Yes, typically. But what if the person who you are invited to consider killing has a strong ambition to kill you at the earliest convenient moment? Or alternatively, what if that person suffers intolerably, with no hope of improvement, ever? Killing can not be said to be categorically wrong under all circumstances - it all depends on the consequences.

Finally, absolutist versions of morality, in the sense that the content of the principle, “X is wrong,” takes precedence over the actual likely outcomes of performing X, are actually demonstrably incoherent. Lay aside the problem of what could possibly be the source of any absolute moral principle. Suppose for a moment that such principles really are set by some divine entity. What then? These moral laws are obviously not physical laws, since we have the capacity to systematically deviate (if we didn’t, they wouldn’t be called moral laws in the first place). Thus, somewhere in the process of our minds, decisions are made about whether or not to follow a particular moral principle at a particular time. If we believe that Godzilla will roast us alive for eternity if we fail to follow the rules, then those predicted consequences are what guide our behaviour. Moral decisions are always the result of a consequentialist evaluation of the options.

Going a little beyond the standard terminology, then, morality is absolute, but with only one rule: “whatever actions are revealed by a rational analysis to be most likely to bring me closer to achieving my goals are the actions I should implement.” This is exactly as I demonstrated in an earlier article on scientific morality. Furthermore, it illustrates that the founding principles of that argument, (1) goodness does not exist outside minds and (2) morality is doing what is good, are both properly basic: they are necessarily correct, and our knowledge of them is not contingent upon empirical observations.

Lets get back to the potential role of retribution in an advanced consequentialist morality. The extent to which the will to see wrongdoers punished is genetically innate, as opposed to culturally transmitted, is certainly an interesting question, and one whose investigation would no doubt require some ingenious experimental protocols. But I strongly suspect that the innateness of these feelings is limited to an extent that can easily be overruled by rationality, allowing vengeance to be effectively eliminated from all consideration in the problem of dealing with criminals. There are several reasons for this suspicion.

Firstly, if we look at the portion of the population most commonly found expressing anger, I’m fairly sure it'll be small children. Anger is, we all recognize, a childish emotion. We grow out of it. We learn (with great relief to most, I presume) to control it, and when as adults we occasionally succumb to emotional outbursts, we typically feel silly afterwards. As advanced society has developed, we have continually learned, oh so painfully slowly, that anger and resentment typically achieve little except the propagation of more anger and resentment. 

Secondly, there seems to be considerable evidence showing that the traditional practices of retributive justice have failed miserably. This paper, for example, argues strongly that imprisonment is ineffective at reducing the frequency and intensity of crime, and that alternative treatments such as education achieve greater reductions of recidivism. Another article summarizes some of its findings: "Research into specific deterrence shows that imprisonment has, at best, no effect on the rate of reoffending and often results in a greater rates of recidivism." The utilitarian advantages of a more rational approach seem to be there for the taking.

Thirdly, whatever memetic components there are, supporting any in-built tendency to desire vengeance, they can, by definition, be overcome by changing our culture.

Fourthly, religious leaders throughout history seem to have made artful use of the philosophy of free will in order to bolster acceptance of their reign of terror (hell doesn’t seem very fair, if all your actions are fixed by the way God set up the boundary conditions, and so damnation only gains a veneer of coherence if we have free will - a notion that evidently has to extend to the mortal plane, in order to justify certain historical hobbies of the major religions). This suggests that the hard-wired machinery of anger was, stripped of any socially conditioned props, insufficient to sustain the required levels of violence in our ever increasingly sophisticated culture.

When it comes to figuring out how to deal with crime, therefore, it is irrational to decide based on a shortsighted lust to see a criminal's debt repaid through suffering. Instead, we must look to scientific data to decide what courses of action minimize the costs to society. We must seek to understand what treatments will cost-effectively turn today's rule breakers into tomorrow's contributors to society, and what measures will economically eliminate the desire and the opportunity to commit crimes in the first place. 




2 comments:

  1. Well - let's define things a little more precisely, shall we?

    When making a decision on legal punishment, we must use a Utility function. We can call the moral utility function consequentialist if it depends only on future well-being - on "what actions will lead to a better society for us, and for our children to grow up in". We can call it absolutist (or "deontological")if it depends only on adhering to certain absolute principles, such as Justice. And we can call it classical (or "virtue ethics") if it depends only on the criminal's state of mind at the time he committed that crime.

    I would suggest our actual utility function is none of the above. We don't want to judge things in a purely consequentialist, deontologist, or virtue-based manner. We have moral intuitions pulling us in all three directions, and in real cases we need to balance them against each other. Falling into the trap of thinking that only one approach is the "right" one is a fallacy.

    Yes, we generally want, as a society, to act in a way that will build a better future for us and our descendants. Consequentialism is not only the baseline, but also the end of all other modes of reasoning - anything that will have dire consequences, will drive us to avoid it.

    Yet consider the Communist Trials. Do we really want to punish the innocent, because it will be for the benefit of society as a whole? Generally speaking - I think not. Justice, that absolute principle, is not without power. We do not want to allow surgeons to pillage the dying for organs to transplant; we do not want to see slavery re-instituted if it is shown to be profitable in some hedonic-calculus; we do not want to kill-off everyone living in the Middle East and re-populate the place with British criminals and religous freaks to re-create another America or Australia (even if such a society would, once established, have much higher well-being). Absolutist considerations count.

    And again, so does virtue-ethics. If person A and person B both killed someone, but person A killed him through premeditated murder and person B through carelesness and bad luck, we would want to treat them differently. Even if punishing them, whichever way, will have the exact same results on our future society.

    What we want is not easy to determine. I doubt it can be reduced to only a single type of utility - like a consequentialist one. And it may very well include retribution, which need not be anchored in juvenile anger. Just like we want distributive justice for others even in rather abstract and remote situations, where we aren't moved to anger at all, so too may we want retributive justice for them. I don't see why this can be ruled out a priori. And I don't see why this can be ruled out due to the fact that we don't have (libertanian) free will.

    Yair

    ReplyDelete
    Replies
    1. Yair,

      Thanks for contributing to the discussion. I'll be brief, perhaps even blunt, since there doesn't seem much point re-iterating everything I have already said.

      You don't seem to have read what I wrote very well. If you think that consequentialism will require us to do things that are bad, then you don't understand consequentialism.

      If you think that consequentialism prevents us treating differently two people who have committed the same basic act, but under different circumstances, then you don't understand consequentialism. As I said, past actions are important as predictors of future behaviour. Anything else that also aids such predictions obviously helps.

      I do not say that retribution can be ruled out a priori, I specifically say that there is no logical connection between libertarian free will and justice, and I argue at length that data are needed to assess the importance of a retributive component.

      You say that we must use a utility function, but it baffles me that you think a rational utility function can be affected by past events, but not not through their impacts on the future (that the utility function can have a non-consequentialist component). This is the only fallacy here. I have demonstrated this at length above, and in a previous post. I urge you to read them more carefully.

      Regards,
      Tom

      Delete